Politics LO512

From: John Conover <john@email.johncon.com>
Subject: Politics LO512
Date: Wed, 22 Mar 95 00:55 PST



My apologies, but I have been watching the recent "gossip" and
"politics" postings. I had written something on the relationship
between politics and game-theory in a different life, a long time ago,
and had trouble finding it. My apologies for the delayed posting.

Consider the following "game." It is, although simple in operation, a
rather complex game, and I will wade through the optimal logic.  The
rules, of this very simplified rendition, of the "game" is as follows:

    There are two players, and each player has only two choices for
    each iteration of the "game," and those choices are to chose
    either "A" or "B." If both players pick "A," then each wins 3
    dollars. If one picks "A," and the other "B," then the player
    picking "B" wins 6 dollars, and the other player gets
    nothing. However, if both players pick "B," then both win 1
    dollar.

It is not a zero-sum game-no player can ever loose any money. So there
is an incentive to always play. Or, to put it in clear, concise form,
the payoff matrix would look like:

                      Player One

                        A     B
                     +-----+-----+
                   A | 3,3 | 6,0 |
        Player two   +-----+-----+
                   B | 6,0 | 1,1 |
                     +-----+-----+

This "game" is what is known to game theorists as the "classic
iterated prisoner's dilemma." The choice "A" is known as a
"cooperation strategy," and the choice "B" is known as the "defection
strategy" for each player. It is a very subtile and devious game. Here
is why, and the logic you would go through. Just before you played,
you would think:

    1) If I pick "A," there are two possible scenarios:

        a) If he picks "A," I would get 3 dollars, and he would get 3
        dollars.

        b) If he picks "B," I would get 1 dollar, and he would get 6
        dollars.

    2) If I pick "B," there are also two possible scenarios:

        a) If he picks "A," I would get 6 dollars, and he would get
        nothing.

        b) If he picks "B," I would get one dollar, and he would get
        one dollar.

Note that by picking "A," the best you could do is to win 3 dollars,
and the worst is to win nothing. But, by picking "B," the best you
could make is 6 dollars, and the worst is one dollar. It would appear,
at least initially, that "B," is the best choice.

But, here is where it gets subtile. You opponent, unless he is stupid,
(correction, "Thinking Challenged," in politically correct
vernacular,) will determine exactly the same strategy, and will never
play "A."  So you both make one dollar every time you play the "game."
But you could make 3 dollars-if you cooperated, by both playing "A."
But if you do that, there is an incentive for either player to play
"B," if he knows the other player is going to play "A," and thus make
6 dollars. And we are right back where we started. Indeed, a very
diabolical "game."

As a simple, empirical, application of the "game," consider the case
of marital dilemma:

    Suppose that marital bliss is upset by a grouchy mate that just
    happens to get up on the wrong side of the bed, (ie., the mate is
    playing a defection strategy-you were playing a cooperation
    strategy, in the interest of preserving the marital bliss.) What
    do you do?  You get grouchy right back, right? And, when the mate
    "comes around," and starts cooperating, you start cooperating, and
    marital bliss is restored. It turns out that this "tit-for-tat"
    strategy is one of the most effective known, and has been recorded
    as a political solution to many dilemmas throughout history, (like
    a "tooth-for-tooth" statement in the Old Testament-there are
    similar statements in Zen, Hinduism, etc.)

This is a key point. Some games have explicit (or statistical,)
solutions. Most don't, and will require a strategy, like
"tit-for-tat." (There are other solutions, and other variants of this
"game" that are far more sophisticated.) How do you separate the
"games" into those that have explicit solutions, and those, like the
iterated prisoner's dilemma that don't?  It turns out that, 1) there
must be an incentive to play the cooperation strategy, and 2) there
must be a larger incentive to play the defection strategy, and 3) if
the defection strategy wins, it must be at the expense of your
opponent, ie., most political situations. For example, it is in a
nation's interest to have a large nuclear stockpile. Naturally, if all
nations adopt this defection strategy, we have a prescription for the
nuclear arms race. So, we have international conferences, that
"equalize" the destructive power of consenting nations (cooperation
strategy,) which is immediately broken by Iraq, etc., (defection
strategy.)

So, is nuclear arms races rational and logical? That depends on your
point of view, but in a strict, logical sense, yes they are.  It is a
rational, logical strategic solution to the iterated prisoner's
dilemma "game." We have to be very carful about making statements that
politics is irrational, when it apparently it has a formal, logical
basis.

Note that all wars in recorded history have been fought to resolve a
question of authority, ie., at least two players, both choosing a
defection strategy. (Note that if only one player chose a defection
strategy, and the other one chose a cooperation strategy, there would
have been no war-and one less nation.)

It should be clear that politics is an essential ingredient of
civilization, if not its defining attribute, (the Greeks considered
"man the political animal,") and is the dynamic operation of
cooperation and defection strategies between players.  Politics and
conflict are inevitable, and unavoidable.

One of the poets in Oruk, the first city in civilization (circa
3000BC, in what is now Iraq,) telling the story of how the gods
delivered civilization to man:

    "I offer you civilization. It will contain farming, commerce, and
    prosperity.  But it will also contain war, greed and famine. And
    you must either take it in whole, or nothing. And once taken, it
    can never be given back."

The rudiments of game-theory are not new.

        John

References:

For "light" reading, see "Prisoner's Dilemma", William Poundstone,
Doubleday, "New York, New York", 1992.

For more rigor, see "Games and Decisions", R. Duncan Luce and Howard
Raiffa, John Wiley & Sons, New York, New York, 1957.

For the relationship of game-theory and human conflict in
civilization, see "The Ascent of Man," J. Bronowski, Little, Brown and
Company, Toronto, 1973.

--

John Conover, john@email.johncon.com, http://www.johncon.com/



Copyright © 1995 John Conover, john@email.johncon.com. All Rights Reserved.
Last modified: Fri Mar 26 18:57:33 PST 1999 $Id: 950322222306.2003.html,v 1.0 2001/11/17 23:05:50 conover Exp $
Valid HTML 4.0!